按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
must get firmly into one's mind that by the judgement of taste (upon the beautiful) the delight in an object is imputed to every one; yet without being founded on a concept (for then it would be the good); and that this claim to universality is such an essential factor of a judgement by which we describe anything as beautiful; that were it not for its being present to the mind it would never enter into any one's head to use this expression; but everything that pleased without a concept would be ranked as agreeable。 For in respect of the agreeable; every one is allowed to have his own opinion; and no one insists upon others agreeing with his judgement of taste; which is what is invariably done in the judgement of taste about beauty。 The first of these I may call the taste of sense; the second; the taste of reflection: the first laying down judgements merely private; the second; on the other hand; judgements ostensibly of general validity (public); but both alike being aesthetic (not practical) judgements about an object merely in respect of the bearings of its representation on the feeling of pleasure or displeasure。 Now it does seem strange that while with the taste of sense it is not alone experience that shows that its judgement (of pleasure or displeasure in something) is not universally valid; but every one willingly refrains from imputing this agreement to others (despite the frequent actual prevalence of a considerable consensus of general opinion even in these judgements); the taste of reflection; which; as experience teaches; has often enough to put up with a rude dismissal of its claims to universal validity of its judgement (upon the beautiful); can (as it actually does) find it possible for all that to formulate judgements capable of demanding this agreement in its universality。 Such agreement it does in fact require from every one for each of its judgements of taste the persons who pass these judgements not quarreling over the possibility of such a claim; but only failing in particular cases to come to terms as to the correct application of this faculty。 First of all we have here to note that a universality which does not rest upon concepts of the object (even though these are only empirical) is in no way logical; but aesthetic; i。 e。; does not involve any objective quantity of the judgement; but only one that is subjective。 For this universality I use the expression general validity; which denotes the validity of the reference of a representation; not to the cognitive faculties; but to the feeling of pleasure or displeasure for every subject。 (The same expression; however; may also be employed for the logical quantity of the judgement; provided we add objective universal validity; to distinguish it from the merely subjective validity which is always aesthetic。) Now a judgement that has objective universal validity has always got the subjective also; i。e。; if the judgement is valid for everything which is contained under a given concept; it is valid also for all who represent an object by means of this concept。 But from a subjective universal validity; i。 e。; the aesthetic; that does not rest on any concept; no conclusion can be drawn to the logical; because judgements of that kind have no bearing upon the object。 But for this very reason the aesthetic universality attributed to a judgement must also be of a special kind; seeing that it does not join the predicate of beauty to the concept of the object taken in its entire logical sphere; and yet does extend this predicate over the whole sphere of judging subjects。 In their logical quantity; all judgements of taste are singular judgements。 For; since I must present the object immediately to my feeling of pleasure or displeasure; and that; too; without the aid of concepts; such judgements cannot have the quantity of judgements with objective general validity。 Yet by taking the singular representation of the object of the judgement of taste; and by comparison converting it into a concept according to the conditions determining that judgement; we can arrive at a logically universal judgement。 For instance; by a judgement of the taste I describe the rose at which I am looking as beautiful。 The judgement; on the other hand; resulting from the comparison of a number of singular representations: 〃Roses in general are beautiful;〃 is no longer pronounced as a purely aesthetic judgement; but as a logical judgement founded on one that is aesthetic。 Now the judgement; 〃The rose is agreeable〃 (to smell) is also; no doubt; an aesthetic and singular judgement; but then it is not one of taste but of sense。 For it has this point of difference from a judgement of taste; that the latter imports an aesthetic quantity of universality; i。e。; of validity for everyone which is not to be met with in a judgement upon the agreeable。 It is only judgements upon the good which; while also determining the delight in an object; possess logical and not mere aesthetic universality; for it is as involving a cognition of the object that 〃they are valid of it; and on that account valid for everyone。 In forming an estimate of objects merely from concepts; all representation of beauty goes by the board。 There can; therefore; be no rule according to which any one is to be compelled to recognize anything as beautiful。 Whether a dress; a house; or a flower is beautiful is a matter upon which one declines to allow one's judgement to be swayed by any reasons or principles。 We want to get a look at the object with our own eyes; just as if our delight depended on sensation。 And yet; if upon so doing; we call the object beautiful; we believe ourselves to be speaking with a universal voice; and lay claim to the concurrence of everyone; whereas no private sensation would be decisive except for the observer alone and his liking。 Here; now; we may perceive that nothing is postulated in the judgement of taste but such a universal voice in respect of delight that it is not mediated by concepts; consequently; only the possibility of an aesthetic judgement capable of being at the same time deemed valid for everyone。 The judgement of taste itself does not postulate the agreement of everyone (for it is only competent for a logically universal judgement to do this; in that it is able to bring forward reasons); it only imputes this agreement to everyone; as an instance of the rule in respect of which it looks for confirmation; not from concepts; but from the concurrence of others。 The universal voice is; therefore; only an idea …resting upon grounds the investigation of which is here postponed。 It may be a matter of uncertainty whether a person who thinks he is laying down a judgement of taste is; in fact; judging in conformity with that idea; but that this idea is what is contemplated in his judgement; and that; consequently; it is meant to be a judgement of taste; is proclaimed by his use of the expression 〃beauty。〃 For himself he can be certain on the point from his mere consciousness of the separation of everything belonging to the agreeable and the good from the delight remaining to him; and this is all for which be promises himself the agreement of everyone…a claim which; under these conditions; he would also be warranted in making; were it not that he frequently sinned against them; and thus passed an erroneous judgement of taste。
SS 9。 Investigation of the question of the relative priority in a judgement of taste of the feeling of pleasure and the estimating of the object。
The solution of this problem is the key to the Critique of taste; and so is worthy of all attention。 Were the pleasure in a given object to be the antecedent; and were the universal communicability of this pleasure to be all that the judgement of taste is meant to allow to the representation of the object; such a sequence would be self…contradictory。 For a pleasure of that kind would be nothing but the feeling of mere agreeableness to the senses; and so; from its very nature; would possess no more than private validity; seeing that it would be immediately dependent on the representation through which the object is given。 Hence it is the universal capacity for being communicated incident to the mental state in the given representation which; as the subjective condition of the judgement of taste; must be; fundamental; with the pleasure in the object as its consequent。 Nothing; however; is capable of being universally communicated but cognition and representation so far as appurtenant to cognition。 For it is only as thus appurtenant that the representation is objective; and it is this alone that gives it a universal point of reference with which the power of representation of every one is obliged to harmonize。 If; then; the determining ground of the judgement as to this universal communicability of the representation is to be merely subjective; that is to say; to be conceived independently of any concept of the object; it can be nothing else than the mental state that presents itself in the mutual relation of the powers of representation so far as they refer a given representation to cognition in general。 The cognitive powers brought into play by this representation are here engaged in a free play; since no definite co