友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
九色书籍 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

the critique of judgement-第7章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!



yed in the cognition of external objects。   But that subjective side of a representation which is incapable of becoming an element of cognition; is the pleasure or displeasure connected with it; for through it I cognize nothing in the object of the representation; although it may easily be the result of the operation of some cognition or other。 Now the finality of a thing; so far as represented in our perception of it; is in no way a quality of the object itself (for a quality of this kind is not one that can be perceived); although it may be inferred from a cognition of things。 In the finality; therefore; which is prior to the cognition of an object; and which; even apart from any desire to make use of the representation of it for the purpose of a cognition; is yet immediately connected with it; we have the subjective quality belonging to it that is incapable of becoming a constituent of knowledge。 Hence we only apply the term final to the object on account of its representation being immediately coupled with the feeling of pleasure: and this representation itself is an aesthetic representation of the finality。 The only question is whether such a representation of finality exists at all。   If pleasure is connected with the mere apprehension (apprehensio) of the form of an object of intuition; apart from any reference it may have to a concept for the purpose of a definite cognition; this does not make the representation referable to the object; but solely to the subject。 In such a case; the pleasure can express nothing but the conformity of the object to the cognitive faculties brought into play in the reflective judgement; and so far as they are in play; and hence merely a subjective formal finality of the object。 For that apprehension of forms in the imagination can never take place without the reflective judgement; even when it has no intention of so doing; comparing them at least with its faculty of referring intuitions to concepts。 If; now; in this comparison; imagination (as the faculty of intuitions a priori) is undesignedly brought into accord with understanding (as the faculty of concepts); by means of a given representation; and a feeling of pleasure is thereby aroused; then the object must be regarded as final for the reflective judgement。 A judgement of this kind is an aesthetic judgement upon the finality of the object; which does not depend upon any present concept of the object; and does not provide one。 When the form of an object (as opposed to the matter of its representation; as sensation) is; in the mere act of reflecting upon it; without regard to any concept to be obtained from it; estimated as the ground of a pleasure in the representation of such an object; then this pleasure is also judged to be combined necessarily with the representation of it; and so not merely for the subject apprehending this form; but for all in general who pass judgement。 The object is then called beautiful; and the faculty of judging by means of such a pleasure (and so also with universal validity) is called taste。 For since the ground of the pleasure is made to reside merely in the form of the object for reflection generally; consequently not in any sensation of the object; and without any reference; either; to any concept that might have something or other in view; it is with the conformity to law in the empirical employment of judgement generally (unity of imagination and understanding) in the subject; and with this alone; that the representation of the object in reflection; the conditions of which are universally valid a priori; accords。 And; as this accordance of the object with the faculties of the subject is contingent; it gives rise to a representation of a finality on the part of the object in respect of the cognitive faculties of the subject。   Here; now; is a pleasure which…as is the case with all pleasure or displeasure that is not brought about through the agency of the concept of freedom (i。e。; through the antecedent determination of the higher faculty of desire by means of pure reason)…no concepts could ever enable us to regard as necessarily connected with the representation of an object。 It must always be only through reflective perception that it is cognized as conjoined with this representation。 As with all empirical judgements; it is; consequently; unable to announce objective necessity or lay claim to a priori validity。 But; then; the judgement of taste in fact only lays claim; like every other empirical judgement; to be valid for every one; and; despite its inner contingency this is always possible。 The only point that is strange or out of the way about it is that it is not an empirical concept; but a feeling of pleasure (and so not a concept at all); that is yet exacted from every one by the judgement of taste; just as if it were a predicate united to the cognition of the object; and that is meant to be conjoined with its representation。   A singular empirical judgement; as for example; the judgement of one who perceives a movable drop of water in a rock…crystal; rightly looks to every one finding the fact as stated; since the judgement has been formed according to the universal conditions of the determinant judgement under the laws of a possible experience generally。 In the same way; one who feels pleasure in simple reflection on the form of an object; without having any concept in mind; rightly lays claim to the agreement of every one; although this judgement is empirical and a singular judgement。 For the ground of this pleasure is found in the universal; though subjective; condition of reflective judgements; namely the final harmony of an object (be it a product of nature or of art) with the mutual relation of the faculties of cognition (imagination and understanding); which are requisite for every empirical cognition。 The pleasure in judgements of taste is; therefore; dependent doubtless on an empirical representation; and cannot be united a priori to any concept (one cannot determine a priori what object will be in accordance with taste or not…one must find out the object that is so); but then it is only made the determining ground of this judgement by virtue of our consciousness of its resting simply upon reflection and the universal; though only subjective; conditions of the harmony of that reflection with the knowledge of objects generally; for which the form of the object is final。   This is why judgements of taste are subjected to a critique in respect of their possibility。 For their possibility presupposes an a priori principle; although that principle is neither a cognitive principle for understanding nor a practical principle for the will; and is thus in no way determinant a priori。   Susceptibility to pleasure arising from reflection on the forms of things (whether of nature or of art) betokens; however; not only a finality on the part of objects in their relation to the reflective judgement in the subject; in accordance with the concept of nature; but also; conversely; a finality on the part of the subject; answering to the concept of freedom; in respect of the form; or even formlessness of objects。 The result is that the aesthetic judgement refers not merely; as a judgement of taste; to the beautiful; but also; as springing from a higher intellectual feeling; to the sublime。 Hence the above…mentioned Critique of Aesthetic judgement must be divided on these lines into two main parts。

           VIII。 The Logical Representation of the                     Finality of Nature。

  There are two ways in which finality may be represented in an object given in experience。 It may be made to turn on what is purely subjective。 In this case the object is considered in respect of its form as present in apprehension (apprehensio) prior to any concept; and the harmony of this form with the cognitive faculties; promoting the combination of the intuition with concepts for cognition generally; is represented as a finality of the form of the object。 Or; on the other hand; the representation of finality may be made to turn on what is objective; in which case it is represented as the harmony of the form of the object with the possibility of the thing itself according to an antecedent concept of it containing the ground of this form。 We have seen that the representation of the former kind of finality rests on the pleasure immediately felt in mere reflection on the form of the object。 But that of the latter kind of finality; as it refers the form of the object; not to the subject's cognitive faculties engaged in its apprehension; but to a definite cognition of the object under a given concept; bas nothing to do with a feeling of pleasure in things; but only understanding and its estimate of them。 Where the concept of an object is given; the function of judgement; in its employment of that concept for cognition; consists in presentation (exhibitio); i。 e。; in placing beside the concept an intuition corresponding to it。 Here it may be that our own imagination is the agent employed; as in the case of art; where we realize a preconceived concept of an object which we set before ourselves as an end。 Or the agent may be nature in its technic (as in the case of organic bodies); when we read into it our own concept of an end to 
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!