友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
九色书籍 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

on sophistical refutations-第12章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!





now in writing that you are seated…a false statement; though it was



true at the time when it was written: therefore the statement that was



written is at the same time false and true。' But this is fallacious;



for the falsity or truth of a statement or opinion indicates not a



substance but a quality: for the same account applies to the case of



an opinion as well。 Again; 'Is what a learner learns what he



learns?' 'Yes。' 'But suppose some one learns 〃slow〃 quick'。 Then his



(the sophist's) words denote not what the learner learns but how he



learns it。 Also; 'Does a man tread upon what he walks through?



'Yes。' 'But X walks through a whole day。' No; rather the words



denote not what he walks through; but when he walks; just as when



any one uses the words 'to drink the cup' he denotes not what he



drinks; but the vessel out of which he drinks。 Also; 'Is it either



by learning or by discovery that a man knows what he knows?' 'Yes。'



'But suppose that of a pair of things he has discovered one and



learned the other; the pair is not known to him by either method。' No:



'what' he knows; means' every single thing' he knows; individually;



but this does not mean 'all the things' he knows; collectively。 Again;



there is the proof that there is a 'third man' distinct from Man and



from individual men。 But that is a fallacy; for 'Man'; and indeed





every general predicate; denotes not an individual substance; but a



particular quality; or the being related to something in a



particular manner; or something of that sort。 Likewise also in the



case of 'Coriscus' and 'Coriscus the musician' there is the problem;



Are they the same or different?' For the one denotes an individual



substance and the other a quality; so that it cannot be isolated;



though it is not the isolation which creates the 'third man'; but



the admission that it is an individual substance。 For 'Man' cannot



be an individual substance; as Callias is。 Nor is the case improved



one whit even if one were to call the clement he has isolated not an



individual substance but a quality: for there will still be the one



beside the many; just as 'Man' was。 It is evident then that one must



not grant that what is a common predicate applying to a class



universally is an individual substance; but must say that denotes



either a quality; or a relation; or a quantity; or something of that



kind。







                                23







  It is a general rule in dealing with arguments that depend on



language that the solution always follows the opposite of the point on



which the argument turns: e。g。 if the argument depends upon



combination; then the solution consists in division; if upon division;



then in combination。 Again; if it depends on an acute accent; the



solution is a grave accent; if on a grave accent; it is an acute。 If



it depends on ambiguity; one can solve it by using the opposite



term; e。g。 if you find yourself calling something inanimate; despite



your previous denial that it was so; show in what sense it is alive:



if; on the other hand; one has declared it to be inanimate and the



sophist has proved it to be animate; say how it is inanimate。 Likewise



also in a case of amphiboly。 If the argument depends on likeness of



expression; the opposite will be the solution。 'Could a man give



what he has not got? 'No; not what he has not got; but he could give



it in a way in which he has not got it; e。g。 one die by itself。'



Does a man know either by learning or by discovery each thing that



he knows; singly? but not the things that he knows; collectively。'



Also a man treads; perhaps; on any thing he walks through; but not



on the time he walks through。 Likewise also in the case of the other



examples。







                                24







  In dealing with arguments that depend on Accident; one and the



same solution meets all cases。 For since it is indeterminate when an



attribute should be ascribed to a thing; in cases where it belongs



to the accident of the thing; and since in some cases it is



generally agreed and people admit that it belongs; while in others



they deny that it need belong; we should therefore; as soon as the



conclusion has been drawn; say in answer to them all alike; that there



is no need for such an attribute to belong。 One must; however; be



prepared to adduce an example of the kind of attribute meant。 All



arguments such as the following depend upon Accident。 'Do you know



what I am going to ask you? you know the man who is approaching'; or



'the man in the mask'? 'Is the statue your work of art?' or 'Is the



dog your father?' 'Is the product of a small number with a small



number a small number?' For it is evident in all these cases that



there is no necessity for the attribute which is true of the thing's



accident to be true of the thing as well。 For only to things that



are indistinguishable and one in essence is it generally agreed that



all the same attributes belong; whereas in the case of a good thing;



to be good is not the same as to be going to be the subject of a



question; nor in the case of a man approaching; or wearing a mask;



is 'to be approaching' the same thing as 'to be Coriscus'; so that



suppose I know Coriscus; but do not know the man who is approaching;



it still isn't the case that I both know and do not know the same man;



nor; again; if this is mine and is also a work of art; is it therefore



my work of art; but my property or thing or something else。 (The



solution is after the same manner in the other cases as well。)



  Some solve these refutations by demolishing the original proposition



asked: for they say that it is possible to know and not to know the



same thing; only not in the same respect: accordingly; when they don't



know the man who is coming towards them; but do know Corsicus; they



assert that they do know and don't know the same object; but not in



the same respect。 Yet; as we have already remarked; the correction



of arguments that depend upon the same point ought to be the same;



whereas this one will not stand if one adopts the same principle in



regard not to knowing something; but to being; or to being is a in a



certain state; e。g。 suppose that X is father; and is also yours: for



if in some cases this is true and it is possible to know and not to



know the same thing; yet with that case the solution stated has



nothing to do。 Certainly there is nothing to prevent the same argument



from having a number of flaws; but it is not the exposition of any and



every fault that constitutes a solution: for it is possible for a



man to show that a false conclusion has been proved; but not to show



on what it depends; e。g。 in the case of Zeno's argument to prove



that motion is impossible。 So that even if any one were to try to



establish that this doctrine is an impossible one; he still is



mistaken; and even if he proved his case ten thousand times over;



still this is no solution of Zeno's argument: for the solution was all



along an exposition of false reasoning; showing on what its falsity



depends。 If then he has not proved his case; or is trying to establish



even a true proposition; or a false one; in a false manner; to point



this out is a true solution。 Possibly; indeed; the present



suggestion may very well apply in some cases: but in these cases; at



any rate; not even this would be generally agreed: for he knows both



that Coriscus is Coriscus and that the approaching figure is



approaching。 To know and not to know the same thing is generally



thought to be possible; when e。g。 one knows that X is white; but



does not realize that he is musical: for in that way he does know



and not know the same thing; though not in the same respect。 But as to



the approaching figure and Coriscus he knows both that it is



approaching and that he is Coriscus。



  A like mistake to that of those whom we have mentioned is that of



those who solve the proof that every number is a small number: for if;



when the conclusion is not proved; they pass this over and say that



a conclusion has been proved and is true; on the ground that every



number is both great and small; they make a mistake。



  Some people also use the principle of ambiguity to solve the



aforesaid reasonings; e。g。 the proof that 'X is your father'; or



'son'; or 'slave'。 Yet it is evident that if the appearance a proof



depends upon a plurality of meanings; the term; or the expression in



question; ought to bear a number of literal senses; whereas no one



speaks of A as being 'B's child' in the literal sense; if B is the



child's master; but the combination depends upon Accident。 'Is A



yours?' 'Yes。' 'And is A a child?' 'Yes。' 'Then the child A is yours;'



because he happens to be both yours and a child; but he is no
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!