友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
九色书籍 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

the science of right-第2章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!




to feel in his mind that reason obliges him to do this; but it means

that he can apply an external compulsion to force any such one so to

pay; and that this compulsion is quite consistent with the freedom

of all; including the parties in question; according to a universal

law。 Right and the title to compel; thus indicate the same thing。



  The law of right; as thus enunciated; is represented as a reciprocal

compulsion necessarily in accordance with the freedom of every one;

under the principle of a universal freedom。 It is thus; as it were;

a representative construction of the conception of right; by

exhibiting it in a pure intuitive perception a priori; after the

analogy of the possibility of the free motions of bodies under the

physical law of the equality of action and reaction。 Now; as in pure

mathematics; we cannot deduce the properties of its objects

immediately from a mere abstract conception; but can only discover

them by figurative construction or representation of its

conceptions; so it is in like manner with the principle of right。 It

is not so much the mere formal conception of right; but rather that of

a universal and equal reciprocal compulsion as harmonizing with it;

and reduced under general laws; that makes representation of that

conception possible。 But just as those conceptions presented in

dynamics are founded upon a merely formal representation of pure

mathematics as presented in geometry; reason has taken care also to

provide the understanding as far as possible with intuitive

presentations a priori in behoof of a construction of the conception

of right。 The right in geometrical lines (rectum) is opposed; as the

straight; to that which is curved and to that which is oblique。 In the

first opposition; there is involved an inner quality of the lines of

such a nature that there is only one straight or right line possible

between two given points。 In the second case; again; the positions

of two intersecting or meeting lines are of such a nature that there

can likewise be only one line called the perpendicular; which is not

more inclined to the one side than the other; and it divides space

on either side into two equal parts。 After the manner of this analogy;

the science of right aims at determining what every one shall have

as his own with mathematical exactness; but this is not to be expected

in the ethical science of virtue; as it cannot but allow a certain

latitude for exceptions。 But; without passing into the sphere of

ethics; there are two cases… known as the equivocal right of equity

and necessity… which claim a juridical decision; yet for which no

one can be found to give such a decision; and which; as regards

their relation to rights; belong; as it were; to the 〃Intermundia〃

of Epicurus。 These we must at the outset take apart from the special

exposition of the science of right; to which we are now about to

advance; and we may consider them now by way of supplement to these

introductory explanations; in order that their uncertain conditions

may not exert a disturbing influence on the fixed principles of the

proper doctrine of right。





          F。 Supplementary Remarks on Equivocal Right。

                       (Jus Aequivocum)。



  With every right; in the strict acceptation (jus strictum); there is

conjoined a right to compel。 But it is possible to think of other

rights of a wider kind (jus latum) in which the title to compel cannot

be determined by any law。 Now there are two real or supposed rights of

this kind… equity and the right of necessity。 The first alleges a

right that is without compulsion; the second adopts a compulsion

that is without right。 This equivocalness; however; can be easily

shown to rest on the peculiar fact that there are cases of doubtful

right; for the decision of which no judge can be appointed。



                          I。 Equity。



  Equity (aequitas); regarded objectively; does not properly

constitute a claim upon the moral duty of benevolence or beneficence

on the part of others; but whoever insists upon anything on the ground

of equity; founds upon his right to the same。 In this case; however;

the conditions are awanting that are requisite for the function of a

judge in order that be might determine what or what kind of

satisfaction can be done to this claim。 When one of the partners of

a mercantile company; formed under the condition of equal profits;

has; however; done more than the other members; and in consequence has

also lost more; it is in accordance with equity that he should

demand from the company more than merely an equal share of advantage

with the rest。 But; in relation to strict right… if we think of a

judge considering his case… he can furnish no definite data to

establish how much more belongs to him by the contract; and in case of

an action at law; such a demand would be rejected。 A domestic servant;

again; who might be paid his wages due to the end of his year of

service in a coinage that became depreciated within that period; so

that it would not be of the same value to him as it was when he

entered on his engagement; cannot claim by right to be kept from

loss on account of the unequal value of the money if he receives the

due amount of it。 He can only make an appeal on the ground of equity;…

a dumb goddess who cannot claim a bearing of right;… because there was

nothing bearing on this point in the contract of service; and a

judge cannot give a decree on the basis of vague or indefinite

conditions。

  Hence it follows; that a court of equity; for the decision of

disputed questions of right; would involve a contradiction。 It is only

where his own proper rights are concerned; and in matters in which

he can decide; that a judge may or ought to give a hearing to

equity。 Thus; if the Crown is supplicated to give an indemnity to

certain persons for loss or injury sustained in its service; it may

undertake the burden of doing so; although; according to strict right;

the claim might be rejected on the ground of the pretext that the

parties in question undertook the performance of the service

occasioning the loss; at their own risk。

  The dictum of equity may be put thus: 〃The strictest right is the

greatest wrong〃 (summum jus summa injuria)。 But this evil cannot be

obviated by the forms of right; although it relates to a matter of

right; for the grievance that it gives rise to can only be put

before a 〃court of conscience〃 (forum poli); whereas every question of

right must be taken before a civil court (forum soli)。



                II。 The Right of Necessity。



  The so…called right of necessity (jus necessitatis) is the

supposed right or title; in case of the danger of losing my own

life; to take away the life of another who has; in fact; done me no

harm。 It is evident that; viewed as a doctrine of right; this must

involve a contradiction; For this is not the case of a wrongful

aggressor making an unjust assault upon my life; and whom I anticipate

by depriving him of his own (jus inculpatae tutelae); nor consequently

is it a question merely of the recommendation of moderation which

belongs to ethics as the doctrine of virtue; and not to

jurisprudence as the doctrine of right。 It is a question of the

allowableness of using violence against one who has used none

against me。

  It is clear that the assertion of such a right is not to be

understood objectively as being in accordance with what a law would

prescribe; but merely subjectively; as proceeding on the assumption of

how a sentence would be pronounced by a court in the case。 There

can; in fact; be no criminal law assigning the penalty of death to a

man who; when shipwrecked and struggling in extreme danger for his

life; and in order to save it; may thrust another from a plank on

which he had saved himself。 For the punishment threatened by the law

could not possibly have greater power than the fear of the loss of

life in the case in question。 Such a penal law would thus fail

altogether to exercise its intended effect; for the threat of an

evil which is still uncertain… such as death by a judicial sentence…

could not overcome the fear of an evil which is certain; as drowning

is in such circumstances。 An act of violent self…preservation; then;

ought not to be considered as altogether beyond condemnation

(inculpabile); it is only to be adjudged as exempt from punishment

(impunibile)。 Yet this subjective condition of impunity; by a

strange confusion of ideas; has been regarded by jurists as equivalent

to objective lawfulness。

  The dictum of the right of necessity is put in these terms:

〃Necessity has no law〃 (Necessitas non habet legem)。 And yet there

cannot be a necessity that could make what is wrong lawful。

  It is apparent; then; that in。 judgements relating both to

〃equity〃 and 〃the right of necessity;〃 the equivocations involved

arise from an interchange of the objective and subjective grou
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!