友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
九色书籍 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

the critique of practical reason-第32章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!



aw is holy (unyielding) and demands holiness of morals; although all the moral perfection to which man can attain is still only virtue; that is; a rightful disposition arising from respect for the law; implying consciousness of a constant propensity to transgression; or at least a want of purity; that is; a mixture of many spurious (not moral) motives of obedience to the law; consequently a self…esteem combined with humility。 In respect; then; of the holiness which the Christian law requires; this leaves the creature nothing but a progress in infinitum; but for that very reason it justifies him in hoping for an endless duration of his existence。 The worth of a character perfectly accordant with the moral law is infinite; since the only restriction on all possible happiness in the judgement of a wise and all powerful distributor of it is the absence of conformity of rational beings to their duty。 But the moral law of itself does not promise any happiness; for according to our conceptions of an order of nature in general; this is not necessarily connected with obedience to the law。 Now Christian morality supplies this defect (of the second indispensable element of the summum bonum) by representing the world in which rational beings devote themselves with all their soul to the moral law; as a kingdom of God; in which nature and morality are brought into a harmony foreign to each of itself; by a holy Author who makes the derived summum bonum possible。 Holiness of life is prescribed to them as a rule even in this life; while the welfare proportioned to it; namely; bliss; is represented as attainable only in an eternity; because the former must always be the pattern of their conduct in every state; and progress towards it is already possible and necessary in this life; while the latter; under the name of happiness; cannot be attained at all in this world (so far as our own power is concerned); and therefore is made simply an object of hope。 Nevertheless; the Christian principle of morality itself is not theological (so as to be heteronomy); but is autonomy of pure practical reason; since it does not make the knowledge of God and His will the foundation of these laws; but only of the attainment of the summum bonum; on condition of following these laws; and it does not even place the proper spring of this obedience in the desired results; but solely in the conception of duty; as that of which the faithful observance alone constitutes the worthiness to obtain those happy consequences。

  *It is commonly held that the Christian precept of morality has no advantage in respect of purity over the moral conceptions of the Stoics; the distinction between them is; however; very obvious。 The Stoic system made the consciousness of strength of mind the pivot on which all moral dispositions should turn; and although its disciples spoke of duties and even defined them very well; yet they placed the spring and proper determining principle of the will in an elevation of the mind above the lower springs of the senses; which owe their power only to weakness of mind。 With them therefore; virtue was a sort of heroism in the wise man raising himself above the animal nature of man; is sufficient for Himself; and; while he prescribes duties to others; is himself raised above them; and is not subject to any temptation to transgress the moral law。 All this; however; they could not have done if they had conceived this law in all its purity and strictness; as the precept of the Gospel does。 When I give the name idea to a perfection to which nothing adequate can be given in experience; it does not follow that the moral ideas are thing transcendent; that is something of which we could not even determine the concept adequately; or of which it is uncertain whether there is any object corresponding to it at all; as is the case with the ideas of speculative reason; on the contrary; being types of practical perfection; they serve as the indispensable rule of conduct and likewise as the standard of comparison。 Now if I consider Christian morals on their philosophical side; then compared with the ideas of the Greek schools; they would appear as follows: the ideas of the Cynics; the Epicureans; the Stoics; and the Christians are: simplicity of nature; prudence; wisdom; and holiness。 In respect of the way of attaining them; the Greek schools were distinguished from one another thus that the Cynics only required common sense; the others the path of science; but both found the mere use of natural powers sufficient for the purpose。 Christian morality; because its precept is framed (as a moral precept must be) so pure and unyielding; takes from man all confidence that be can be fully adequate to it; at least in this life; but again sets it up by enabling us to hope that if we act as well as it is in our power to do; then what is not in our power will come in to our aid from another source; whether we know how this may be or not。 Aristotle and Plato differed only as to the origin of our moral conceptions。

  In this manner; the moral laws lead through the conception of the summum bonum as the object and final end of pure practical reason to religion; that is; to the recognition of all duties as divine commands; not as sanctions; that is to say; arbitrary ordinances of a foreign and contingent in themselves; but as essential laws of every free will in itself; which; nevertheless; must be regarded as commands of the Supreme Being; because it is only from a morally perfect (holy and good) and at the same time all…powerful will; and consequently only through harmony with this will; that we can hope to attain the summum bonum which the moral law makes it our duty to take as the object of our endeavours。 Here again; then; all remains disinterested and founded merely on duty; neither fear nor hope being made the fundamental springs; which if taken as principles would destroy the whole moral worth of actions。 The moral law commands me to make the highest possible good in a world the ultimate object of all my conduct。 But I cannot hope to effect this otherwise than by the harmony of my will with that of a holy and good Author of the world; and although the conception of the summum bonum as a whole; in which the greatest happiness is conceived as combined in the most exact proportion with the highest degree of moral perfection (possible in creatures); includes my own happiness; yet it is not this that is the determining principle of the will which is enjoined to promote the summum bonum; but the moral law; which; on the contrary; limits by strict conditions my unbounded desire of happiness。   Hence also morality is not properly the doctrine how we should make ourselves happy; but how we should become worthy of happiness。 It is only when religion is added that there also comes in the hope of participating some day in happiness in proportion as we have endeavoured to be not unworthy of it。   A man is worthy to possess a thing or a state when his possession of it is in harmony with the summum bonum。 We can now easily see that all worthiness depends on moral conduct; since in the conception of the summum bonum this constitutes the condition of the rest (which belongs to one's state); namely; the participation of happiness。 Now it follows from this that morality should never be treated as a doctrine of happiness; that is; an instruction how to become happy; for it has to do simply with the rational condition (conditio sine qua non) of happiness; not with the means of attaining it。 But when morality has been completely expounded (which merely imposes duties instead of providing rules for selfish desires); then first; after the moral desire to promote the summum bonum (to bring the kingdom of God to us) has been awakened; a desire founded on a law; and which could not previously arise in any selfish mind; and when for the behoof of this desire the step to religion has been taken; then this ethical doctrine may be also called a doctrine of happiness because the hope of happiness first begins with religion only。   We can also see from this that; when we ask what is God's ultimate end in creating the world; we must not name the happiness of the rational beings in it; but the summum bonum; which adds a further condition to that wish of such beings; namely; the condition of being worthy of happiness; that is; the morality of these same rational beings; a condition which alone contains the rule by which only they can hope to share in the former at the hand of a wise Author。 For as wisdom; theoretically considered; signifies the knowledge of the summum bonum and; practically; the accordance of the will with the summum bonum; we cannot attribute to a supreme independent wisdom an end based merely on goodness。 For we cannot conceive the action of this goodness (in respect of the happiness of rational beings) as suitable to the highest original good; except under the restrictive conditions of harmony with the holiness* of his will。 Therefore; those who placed the end of creation in the glory of God (provided that this is not conceived anthropomorphically as a desire to be praised) have perhaps hit upon the best expression。 For nothing glorifies God more than that which is the most estimable thing in the world;
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!