友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
九色书籍 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

the critique of practical reason-第33章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!



expression。 For nothing glorifies God more than that which is the most estimable thing in the world; respect for his command; the observance of the holy duty that his law imposes on us; when there is added thereto his glorious plan of crowning such a beautiful order of things with corresponding happiness。 If the latter (to speak humanly) makes Him worthy of love; by the former He is an object of adoration。 Even men can never acquire respect by benevolence alone; though they may gain love; so that the greatest beneficence only procures them honour when it is regulated by worthiness。

  *In order to make these characteristics of these conceptions clear; I add the remark that whilst we ascribe to God various attributes; the quality of which we also find applicable to creatures; only that in Him they are raised to the highest degree; e。g。; power; knowledge; presence; goodness; etc。; under the designations of omnipotence; omniscience; omnipresence; etc。; there are three that are ascribed to God exclusively; and yet without the addition of greatness; and which are all moral He is the only holy; the only blessed; the only wise; because these conceptions already imply the absence of limitation。 In the order of these attributes He is also the holy lawgiver (and creator); the good governor (and preserver) and the just judge; three attributes which include everything by which God is the object of religion; and in conformity with which the metaphysical perfections are added of themselves in the reason。

  That in the order of ends; man (and with him every rational being) is an end in himself; that is; that he can never be used merely as a means by any (not even by God) without being at the same time an end also himself; that therefore humanity in our person must be holy to ourselves; this follows now of itself because he is the subject of the moral law; in other words; of that which is holy in itself; and on account of which and in agreement with which alone can anything be termed holy。 For this moral law is founded on the autonomy of his will; as a free will which by its universal laws must necessarily be able to agree with that to which it is to submit itself。

    VI。 Of the Postulates of Pure Practical Reason Generally。

  They all proceed from the principle of morality; which is not a postulate but a law; by which reason determines the will directly; which will; because it is so determined as a pure will; requires these necessary conditions of obedience to its precept。 These postulates are not theoretical dogmas but; suppositions practically necessary; while then they do 'not' extend our speculative knowledge; they give objective reality to the ideas of speculative reason in general (by means of their reference to what is practical); and give it a right to concepts; the possibility even of which it could not otherwise venture to affirm。   These postulates are those of immortality; freedom positively considered (as the causality of a being so far as he belongs to the intelligible world); and the existence of God。 The first results from the practically necessary condition of a duration adequate to the complete fulfilment of the moral law; the second from the necessary supposition of independence of the sensible world; and of the faculty of determining one's will according to the law of an intelligible world; that is; of freedom; the third from the necessary condition of the existence of the summum bonum in such an intelligible world; by the supposition of the supreme independent good; that is; the existence of God。   Thus the fact that respect for the moral law necessarily makes the summum bonum an object of our endeavours; and the supposition thence resulting of its objective reality; lead through the postulates of practical reason to conceptions which speculative reason might indeed present as problems; but could never solve。 Thus it leads: 1。 To that one in the solution of which the latter could do nothing but commit paralogisms (namely; that of immortality); because it could not lay hold of the character of permanence; by which to complete the psychological conception of an ultimate subject necessarily ascribed to the soul in self…consciousness; so as to make it the real conception of a substance; a character which practical reason furnishes by the postulate of a duration required for accordance with the moral law in the summum bonum; which is the whole end of practical reason。 2。 It leads to that of which speculative reason contained nothing but antinomy; the solution of which it could only found on a notion Problematically conceivable indeed; but whose objective reality it could not prove or determine; namely; the cosmological idea of an intelligible world and the consciousness of our existence in it; by means of the postulate of freedom (the reality of which it lays down by virtue of the moral law); and with it likewise the law of an intelligible world; to which speculative reason could only point; but could not define its conception。 3。 What speculative reason was able to think; but was obliged to leave undetermined as a mere transcendental ideal; viz。; the theological conception of the first Being; to this it gives significance (in a practical view; that is; as a condition of the possibility of the object of a will determined by that law); namely; as the supreme principle of the summum bonum in an intelligible world; by means of moral legislation in it invested with sovereign power。   Is our knowledge; however; actually extended in this way by pure practical reason; and is that immanent in practical reason which for the speculative was only transcendent? Certainly; but only in a practical point of view。 For we do not thereby take knowledge of the nature of our souls; nor of the intelligible world; nor of the Supreme Being; with respect to what they are in themselves; but we have merely combined the conceptions of them in the practical concept of the summum bonum as the object of our will; and this altogether a priori; but only by means of the moral law; and merely in reference to it; in respect of the object which it commands。 But how freedom is possible; and how we are to conceive this kind of causality theoretically and positively; is not thereby discovered; but only that there is such a causality is postulated by the moral law and in its behoof。 It is the same with the remaining ideas; the possibility of which no human intelligence will ever fathom; but the truth of which; on the other hand; no sophistry will ever wrest from the conviction even of the commonest man。

  VII。 How is it possible to conceive an Extension of Pure        Reason in a Practical point of view; without its           Knowledge as Speculative being enlarged at                       the same time?

  In order not to be too abstract; we will answer this question at once in its application to the present case。 In order to extend a pure cognition practically; there must be an a priori purpose given; that is; an end as object (of the will); which independently of all theological principle is presented as practically necessary by an imperative which determines the will directly (a categorical imperative); and in this case that is the summum bonum。 This; however; is not possible without presupposing three theoretical conceptions (for which; because they are mere conceptions of pure reason; no corresponding intuition can be found; nor consequently by the path of theory any objective reality); namely; freedom; immortality; and God。 Thus by the practical law which commands the existence of the highest good possible in a world; the possibility of those objects of pure speculative reason is postulated; and the objective reality which the latter could not assure them。 By this the theoretical knowledge of pure reason does indeed obtain an accession; but it consists only in this; that those concepts which otherwise it had to look upon as problematical (merely thinkable) concepts; are now shown assertorially to be such as actually have objects; because practical reason indispensably requires their existence for the possibility of its object; the summum bonum; which practically is absolutely necessary; and this justifies theoretical reason in assuming them。 But this extension of theoretical reason is no extension of speculative; that is; we cannot make any positive use of it in a theoretical point of view。 For as nothing is accomplished in this by practical reason; further than that these concepts are real and actually have their (possible) objects; and nothing in the way of intuition of them is given thereby (which indeed could not be demanded); hence the admission of this reality does not render any synthetical proposition possible。 Consequently; this discovery does not in the least help us to extend this knowledge of ours in a speculative point of view; although it does in respect of the practical employment of pure reason。 The above three ideas of speculative reason are still in themselves not cognitions; they are however (transcendent) thoughts; in which there is nothing impossible。 Now; by help of an apodeictic practical law; being necessary conditions of that which it commands to be made an object; they acquire objective reality; that is; we learn from it that t
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!