友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
九色书籍 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

prior analytics-第29章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






conclusion would not depend on the original hypothesis。 Or again trace



the connexion upwards; e。g。 suppose that A belongs to B; E to A and



F to E; it being false that F belongs to A。 In this way too the



impossible conclusion would result; though the original hypothesis



were eliminated。 But the impossible conclusion ought to be connected



with the original terms: in this way it will depend on the hypothesis;



e。g。 when one traces the connexion downwards; the impossible



conclusion must be connected with that term which is predicate in



the hypothesis: for if it is impossible that A should belong to D; the



false conclusion will no longer result after A has been eliminated。 If



one traces the connexion upwards; the impossible conclusion must be



connected with that term which is subject in the hypothesis: for if it



is impossible that F should belong to B; the impossible conclusion



will disappear if B is eliminated。 Similarly when the syllogisms are



negative。



  It is clear then that when the impossibility is not related to the



original terms; the false conclusion does not result on account of the



assumption。 Or perhaps even so it may sometimes be independent。 For if



it were laid down that A belongs not to B but to K; and that K belongs



to C and C to D; the impossible conclusion would still stand。



Similarly if one takes the terms in an ascending series。



Consequently since the impossibility results whether the first



assumption is suppressed or not; it would appear to be independent



of that assumption。 Or perhaps we ought not to understand the



statement that the false conclusion results independently of the



assumption; in the sense that if something else were supposed the



impossibility would result; but rather we mean that when the first



assumption is eliminated; the same impossibility results through the



remaining premisses; since it is not perhaps absurd that the same



false result should follow from several hypotheses; e。g。 that



parallels meet; both on the assumption that the interior angle is



greater than the exterior and on the assumption that a triangle



contains more than two right angles。







                                18







  A false argument depends on the first false statement in it。 Every



syllogism is made out of two or more premisses。 If then the false



conclusion is drawn from two premisses; one or both of them must be



false: for (as we proved) a false syllogism cannot be drawn from two



premisses。 But if the premisses are more than two; e。g。 if C is



established through A and B; and these through D; E; F; and G; one



of these higher propositions must be false; and on this the argument



depends: for A and B are inferred by means of D; E; F; and G。



Therefore the conclusion and the error results from one of them。







                                19







  In order to avoid having a syllogism drawn against us we must take



care; whenever an opponent asks us to admit the reason without the



conclusions; not to grant him the same term twice over in his



premisses; since we know that a syllogism cannot be drawn without a



middle term; and that term which is stated more than once is the



middle。 How we ought to watch the middle in reference to each



conclusion; is evident from our knowing what kind of thesis is



proved in each figure。 This will not escape us since we know how we



are maintaining the argument。



  That which we urge men to beware of in their admissions; they



ought in attack to try to conceal。 This will be possible first; if;



instead of drawing the conclusions of preliminary syllogisms; they



take the necessary premisses and leave the conclusions in the dark;



secondly if instead of inviting assent to propositions which are



closely connected they take as far as possible those that are not



connected by middle terms。 For example suppose that A is to be



inferred to be true of F; B; C; D; and E being middle terms。 One ought



then to ask whether A belongs to B; and next whether D belongs to E;



instead of asking whether B belongs to C; after that he may ask



whether B belongs to C; and so on。 If the syllogism is drawn through



one middle term; he ought to begin with that: in this way he will most



likely deceive his opponent。







                                20







  Since we know when a syllogism can be formed and how its terms



must be related; it is clear when refutation will be possible and when



impossible。 A refutation is possible whether everything is conceded;



or the answers alternate (one; I mean; being affirmative; the other



negative)。 For as has been shown a syllogism is possible whether the



terms are related in affirmative propositions or one proposition is



affirmative; the other negative: consequently; if what is laid down is



contrary to the conclusion; a refutation must take place: for a



refutation is a syllogism which establishes the contradictory。 But



if nothing is conceded; a refutation is impossible: for no syllogism



is possible (as we saw) when all the terms are negative: therefore



no refutation is possible。 For if a refutation were possible; a



syllogism must be possible; although if a syllogism is possible it



does not follow that a refutation is possible。 Similarly refutation is



not possible if nothing is conceded universally: since the fields of



refutation and syllogism are defined in the same way。







                                21







  It sometimes happens that just as we are deceived in the arrangement



of the terms; so error may arise in our thought about them; e。g。 if it



is possible that the same predicate should belong to more than one



subject immediately; but although knowing the one; a man may forget



the other and think the opposite true。 Suppose that A belongs to B and



to C in virtue of their nature; and that B and C belong to all D in



the same way。 If then a man thinks that A belongs to all B; and B to



D; but A to no C; and C to all D; he will both know and not know the



same thing in respect of the same thing。 Again if a man were to make a



mistake about the members of a single series; e。g。 suppose A belongs



to B; B to C; and C to D; but some one thinks that A belongs to all B;



but to no C: he will both know that A belongs to D; and think that



it does not。 Does he then maintain after this simply that what he



knows; he does not think? For he knows in a way that A belongs to C



through B; since the part is included in the whole; so that what he



knows in a way; this he maintains he does not think at all: but that



is impossible。



  In the former case; where the middle term does not belong to the



same series; it is not possible to think both the premisses with



reference to each of the two middle terms: e。g。 that A belongs to



all B; but to no C; and both B and C belong to all D。 For it turns out



that the first premiss of the one syllogism is either wholly or



partially contrary to the first premiss of the other。 For if he thinks



that A belongs to everything to which B belongs; and he knows that B



belongs to D; then he knows that A belongs to D。 Consequently if again



he thinks that A belongs to nothing to which C belongs; he thinks that



A does not belong to some of that to which B belongs; but if he thinks



that A belongs to everything to which B belongs; and again thinks that



A does not belong to some of that to which B belongs; these beliefs



are wholly or partially contrary。 In this way then it is not



possible to think; but nothing prevents a man thinking one premiss



of each syllogism of both premisses of one of the two syllogisms: e。g。



A belongs to all B; and B to D; and again A belongs to no C。 An



error of this kind is similar to the error into which we fall



concerning particulars: e。g。 if A belongs to all B; and B to all C;



A will belong to all C。 If then a man knows that A belongs to



everything to which B belongs; he knows that A belongs to C。 But



nothing prevents his being ignorant that C exists; e。g。 let A stand



for two right angles; B for triangle; C for a particular diagram of



a triangle。 A man might think that C did not exist; though he knew



that every triangle contains two right angles; consequently he will



know and not know the same thing at the same time。 For the



expression 'to know that every triangle has its angles equal to two



right angles' is ambiguous; meaning to have the knowledge either of



the universal or of the particulars。 Thus then he knows that C



contains two right angles with a
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!