友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
九色书籍 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

prior analytics-第4章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






indefinite; it may be used truly of that also which belongs to none。



But if R belongs to no S; no syllogism is possible; as has been shown。



Clearly then no syllogism will be possible here。



  But if the negative term is universal; whenever the major is



negative and the minor affirmative there will be a syllogism。 For if P



belongs to no S; and R belongs to some S; P will not belong to some R:



for we shall have the first figure again; if the premiss RS is



converted。



  But when the minor is negative; there will be no syllogism。 Terms



for the positive relation are animal; man; wild: for the negative



relation; animal; science; wild…the middle in both being the term



wild。



  Nor is a syllogism possible when both are stated in the negative;



but one is universal; the other particular。 When the minor is



related universally to the middle; take the terms animal; science;



wild; animal; man; wild。 When the major is related universally to



the middle; take as terms for a negative relation raven; snow;



white。 For a positive relation terms cannot be found; if R belongs



to some S; and does not belong to some S。 For if P belongs to all R;



and R to some S; then P belongs to some S: but we assumed that it



belongs to no S。 Our point; then; must be proved from the indefinite



nature of the particular statement。



  Nor is a syllogism possible anyhow; if each of the extremes



belongs to some of the middle or does not belong; or one belongs and



the other does not to some of the middle; or one belongs to some of



the middle; the other not to all; or if the premisses are



indefinite。 Common terms for all are animal; man; white: animal;



inanimate; white。



  It is clear then in this figure also when a syllogism will be



possible; and when not; and that if the terms are as stated; a



syllogism results of necessity; and if there is a syllogism; the terms



must be so related。 It is clear also that all the syllogisms in this



figure are imperfect (for all are made perfect by certain



supplementary assumptions); and that it will not be possible to



reach a universal conclusion by means of this figure; whether negative



or affirmative。







                                 7







  It is evident also that in all the figures; whenever a proper



syllogism does not result; if both the terms are affirmative or



negative nothing necessary follows at all; but if one is



affirmative; the other negative; and if the negative is stated



universally; a syllogism always results relating the minor to the



major term; e。g。 if A belongs to all or some B; and B belongs to no C:



for if the premisses are converted it is necessary that C does not



belong to some A。 Similarly also in the other figures: a syllogism



always results by means of conversion。 It is evident also that the



substitution of an indefinite for a particular affirmative will effect



the same syllogism in all the figures。



  It is clear too that all the imperfect syllogisms are made perfect



by means of the first figure。 For all are brought to a conclusion



either ostensively or per impossibile。 In both ways the first figure



is formed: if they are made perfect ostensively; because (as we saw)



all are brought to a conclusion by means of conversion; and conversion



produces the first figure: if they are proved per impossibile; because



on the assumption of the false statement the syllogism comes about



by means of the first figure; e。g。 in the last figure; if A and B



belong to all C; it follows that A belongs to some B: for if A



belonged to no B; and B belongs to all C; A would belong to no C:



but (as we stated) it belongs to all C。 Similarly also with the rest。



  It is possible also to reduce all syllogisms to the universal



syllogisms in the first figure。 Those in the second figure are clearly



made perfect by these; though not all in the same way; the universal



syllogisms are made perfect by converting the negative premiss; each



of the particular syllogisms by reductio ad impossibile。 In the



first figure particular syllogisms are indeed made perfect by



themselves; but it is possible also to prove them by means of the



second figure; reducing them ad impossibile; e。g。 if A belongs to



all B; and B to some C; it follows that A belongs to some C。 For if it



belonged to no C; and belongs to all B; then B will belong to no C:



this we know by means of the second figure。 Similarly also



demonstration will be possible in the case of the negative。 For if A



belongs to no B; and B belongs to some C; A will not belong to some C:



for if it belonged to all C; and belongs to no B; then B will belong



to no C: and this (as we saw) is the middle figure。 Consequently;



since all syllogisms in the middle figure can be reduced to



universal syllogisms in the first figure; and since particular



syllogisms in the first figure can be reduced to syllogisms in the



middle figure; it is clear that particular syllogisms can be reduced



to universal syllogisms in the first figure。 Syllogisms in the third



figure; if the terms are universal; are directly made perfect by means



of those syllogisms; but; when one of the premisses is particular;



by means of the particular syllogisms in the first figure: and these



(we have seen) may be reduced to the universal syllogisms in the first



figure: consequently also the particular syllogisms in the third



figure may be so reduced。 It is clear then that all syllogisms may



be reduced to the universal syllogisms in the first figure。



  We have stated then how syllogisms which prove that something



belongs or does not belong to something else are constituted; both how



syllogisms of the same figure are constituted in themselves; and how



syllogisms of different figures are related to one another。







                                 8







  Since there is a difference according as something belongs;



necessarily belongs; or may belong to something else (for many



things belong indeed; but not necessarily; others neither



necessarily nor indeed at all; but it is possible for them to belong);



it is clear that there will be different syllogisms to prove each of



these relations; and syllogisms with differently related terms; one



syllogism concluding from what is necessary; another from what is; a



third from what is possible。



  There is hardly any difference between syllogisms from necessary



premisses and syllogisms from premisses which merely assert。 When



the terms are put in the same way; then; whether something belongs



or necessarily belongs (or does not belong) to something else; a



syllogism will or will not result alike in both cases; the only



difference being the addition of the expression 'necessarily' to the



terms。 For the negative statement is convertible alike in both



cases; and we should give the same account of the expressions 'to be



contained in something as in a whole' and 'to be predicated of all



of something'。 With the exceptions to be made below; the conclusion



will be proved to be necessary by means of conversion; in the same



manner as in the case of simple predication。 But in the middle



figure when the universal statement is affirmative; and the particular



negative; and again in the third figure when the universal is



affirmative and the particular negative; the demonstration will not



take the same form; but it is necessary by the 'exposition' of a



part of the subject of the particular negative proposition; to which



the predicate does not belong; to make the syllogism in reference to



this: with terms so chosen the conclusion will necessarily follow。 But



if the relation is necessary in respect of the part taken; it must



hold of some of that term in which this part is included: for the part



taken is just some of that。 And each of the resulting syllogisms is in



the appropriate figure。







                                 9







  It happens sometimes also that when one premiss is necessary the



conclusion is necessary; not however when either premiss is necessary;



but only when the major is; e。g。 if A is taken as necessarily



belonging or not belonging to B; but B is taken as simply belonging to



C: for if the premisses are taken in this way; A will necessarily



belong or not belong to C。 For since necessarily belongs; or does



not belong; to every B; and since C is one of the Bs; it is clear that



for C also the positive or the negative relation to A will hold



necessarily。 But if the major premiss is not necessary; but the



minor i
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!