友情提示:如果本网页打开太慢或显示不完整,请尝试鼠标右键“刷新”本网页!阅读过程发现任何错误请告诉我们,谢谢!! 报告错误
九色书籍 返回本书目录 我的书架 我的书签 TXT全本下载 进入书吧 加入书签

prior analytics-第6章

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!





should belong to some C; but it is possible for A to belong to C;



and that A should belong to B is not necessary。 For there is no



necessity that some biped should be asleep or awake。 Similarly and



by means of the same terms proof can be made; should the proposition



AC be both particular and necessary。



  But if one premiss is affirmative; the other negative; whenever



the universal is both negative and necessary the conclusion also



will be necessary。 For if it is not possible that A should belong to



any C; but B belongs to some C; it is necessary that A should not



belong to some B。 But whenever the affirmative proposition is



necessary; whether universal or particular; or the negative is



particular; the conclusion will not be necessary。 The proof of this by



reduction will be the same as before; but if terms are wanted; when



the universal affirmative is necessary; take the terms



'waking'…'animal'…'man'; 'man' being middle; and when the



affirmative is particular and necessary; take the terms



'waking'…'animal'…'white': for it is necessary that animal should



belong to some white thing; but it is possible that waking should



belong to none; and it is not necessary that waking should not



belong to some animal。 But when the negative proposition being



particular is necessary; take the terms 'biped'; 'moving'; 'animal';



'animal' being middle。



                                12







  It is clear then that a simple conclusion is not reached unless both



premisses are simple assertions; but a necessary conclusion is



possible although one only of the premisses is necessary。 But in



both cases; whether the syllogisms are affirmative or negative; it



is necessary that one premiss should be similar to the conclusion。 I



mean by 'similar'; if the conclusion is a simple assertion; the



premiss must be simple; if the conclusion is necessary; the premiss



must be necessary。 Consequently this also is clear; that the



conclusion will be neither necessary nor simple unless a necessary



or simple premiss is assumed。







                                13







  Perhaps enough has been said about the proof of necessity; how it



comes about and how it differs from the proof of a simple statement。



We proceed to discuss that which is possible; when and how and by what



means it can be proved。 I use the terms 'to be possible' and 'the



possible' of that which is not necessary but; being assumed; results



in nothing impossible。 We say indeed ambiguously of the necessary that



it is possible。 But that my definition of the possible is correct is



clear from the phrases by which we deny or on the contrary affirm



possibility。 For the expressions 'it is not possible to belong'; 'it



is impossible to belong'; and 'it is necessary not to belong' are



either identical or follow from one another; consequently their



opposites also; 'it is possible to belong'; 'it is not impossible to



belong'; and 'it is not necessary not to belong'; will either be



identical or follow from one another。 For of everything the



affirmation or the denial holds good。 That which is possible then will



be not necessary and that which is not necessary will be possible。



It results that all premisses in the mode of possibility are



convertible into one another。 I mean not that the affirmative are



convertible into the negative; but that those which are affirmative in



form admit of conversion by opposition; e。g。 'it is possible to



belong' may be converted into 'it is possible not to belong'; and



'it is possible for A to belong to all B' into 'it is possible for A



to belong to no B' or 'not to all B'; and 'it is possible for A to



belong to some B' into 'it is possible for A not to belong to some B'。



And similarly the other propositions in this mode can be converted。



For since that which is possible is not necessary; and that which is



not necessary may possibly not belong; it is clear that if it is



possible that A should belong to B; it is possible also that it should



not belong to B: and if it is possible that it should belong to all;



it is also possible that it should not belong to all。 The same holds



good in the case of particular affirmations: for the proof is



identical。 And such premisses are affirmative and not negative; for



'to be possible' is in the same rank as 'to be'; as was said above。



  Having made these distinctions we next point out that the expression



'to be possible' is used in two ways。 In one it means to happen



generally and fall short of necessity; e。g。 man's turning grey or



growing or decaying; or generally what naturally belongs to a thing



(for this has not its necessity unbroken; since man's existence is not



continuous for ever; although if a man does exist; it comes about



either necessarily or generally)。 In another sense the expression



means the indefinite; which can be both thus and not thus; e。g。 an



animal's walking or an earthquake's taking place while it is



walking; or generally what happens by chance: for none of these



inclines by nature in the one way more than in the opposite。



  That which is possible in each of its two senses is convertible into



its opposite; not however in the same way: but what is natural is



convertible because it does not necessarily belong (for in this



sense it is possible that a man should not grow grey) and what is



indefinite is convertible because it inclines this way no more than



that。 Science and demonstrative syllogism are not concerned with



things which are indefinite; because the middle term is uncertain; but



they are concerned with things that are natural; and as a rule



arguments and inquiries are made about things which are possible in



this sense。 Syllogisms indeed can be made about the former; but it



is unusual at any rate to inquire about them。



  These matters will be treated more definitely in the sequel; our



business at present is to state the moods and nature of the



syllogism made from possible premisses。 The expression 'it is possible



for this to belong to that' may be understood in two senses: 'that'



may mean either that to which 'that' belongs or that to which it may



belong; for the expression 'A is possible of the subject of B' means



that it is possible either of that of which B is stated or of that



of which B may possibly be stated。 It makes no difference whether we



say; A is possible of the subject of B; or all B admits of A。 It is



clear then that the expression 'A may possibly belong to all B'



might be used in two senses。 First then we must state the nature and



characteristics of the syllogism which arises if B is possible of



the subject of C; and A is possible of the subject of B。 For thus both



premisses are assumed in the mode of possibility; but whenever A is



possible of that of which B is true; one premiss is a simple



assertion; the other a problematic。 Consequently we must start from



premisses which are similar in form; as in the other cases。







                                14







  Whenever A may possibly belong to all B; and B to all C; there



will be a perfect syllogism to prove that A may possibly belong to all



C。 This is clear from the definition: for it was in this way that we



explained 'to be possible for one term to belong to all of another'。



Similarly if it is possible for A to belong no B; and for B to



belong to all C; then it is possible for A to belong to no C。 For



the statement that it is possible for A not to belong to that of which



B may be true means (as we saw) that none of those things which can



possibly fall under the term B is left out of account。 But whenever



A may belong to all B; and B may belong to no C; then indeed no



syllogism results from the premisses assumed; but if the premiss BC is



converted after the manner of problematic propositions; the same



syllogism results as before。 For since it is possible that B should



belong to no C; it is possible also that it should belong to all C。



This has been stated above。 Consequently if B is possible for all C;



and A is possible for all B; the same syllogism again results。



Similarly if in both the premisses the negative is joined with 'it



is possible': e。g。 if A may belong to none of the Bs; and B to none of



the Cs。 No syllogism results from the assumed premisses; but if they



are converted we shall have the same syllogism as before。 It is



clear then that if the minor premiss is negative; or if both premisses



are negative; either no syllogism results; or if one it is not



perfe
返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0
未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
温馨提示: 温看小说的同时发表评论,说出自己的看法和其它小伙伴们分享也不错哦!发表书评还可以获得积分和经验奖励,认真写原创书评 被采纳为精评可以获得大量金币、积分和经验奖励哦!